May's Theorem
May's Theorem is a Voting Theory theorem
Desirable Properties
- Neutrality - we don't look at the names of candidates
- Anonymity - we just count the votes without looking at the names of voters
- Monotonicity
Theorem
With two candidates ($A = \{a, b\}$) the only voting mechanism that satisfies all these three properties is Plurality Voting
- Anonymity
- the only possible thing to do is to count the number of voters that prefer $a$ to $b$ and $b$ to $a$:
- let $N(a > b)$ denote the number of people who prefer $a$ to $b$ and $N(b > a)$ - $b$ to $a$
- by neutrality we can say without loss of generality that $N(a > b) > N(b > a)$
For the case when $N(a > b) > N(b > a)$ there are two possible outcomes:
- $a$ is elected - this case is the Plurality Voting case
- $b$ is elected - not Plurality Voting
Case 2
- $N(a > b) > N(b > a)$ but $b$ wins over $a$ - let's show that this assumption leads to contradiction
So suppose that the candidate who receives less votes gets elected
- $N(a > b) > N(b > a) \Rightarrow N(a > b) = N(b > a) + k$ for some $k > 0$
- by applying the Monotonicity principle (we assume it's satisfied) we improve $b$'s position:
- $N(a > b) = N(b > a) + 1$: $b$ still gets elected
- continue improving $b$'s positions
- $N(a > b) = N(b > a) - k' \Rightarrow N(a > b) < N(b > a)$
- since the candidate with fewer votes gets elected, not $a$ wins
- thus Monotonicity is not satisfied: by improving his position $b$ no longer wins
- contradiction: by monotonicity $b$ should remain elected, but by the assumption - $a$
Therefore the only possible outcome under the assumed principles is $a$ wins - which is the Plurality Voting mechanism.
$\square$
See also
Sources